Search Results for: papers/490937

Zombies, Androids, Pantomines

Go

The Basic Argument

  1. Brain states qua physical states exist and mental states exist.
  2. Mental states possess properties that physical states and systems do not.
  3. Brain states are not identical to mental states.

The Indiscernibilty of Identicals

Statements of identity are usually analyzed as follows: for any entities x and y, if x and y are really the same thing, then for any property P, P is true of x if and only if P is true of y. Note that, with respect to mind/brain identity, the principle is indifferent to whether mind is inseparable from the brain and whether the mind is correlated to the brain in a law-like fashion.

Properties of Physical Things

  1. Resistance (traditionally, hardness or solidity)
  2. Mass
  3. Velocity
  4. Charge

Possibly Unique Properties of Mental States

  1. Qualia and Secondary Properties
  2. Self-Presenting Properties. Privacy and Incorrigibility.
  3. The Subjective Nature of Experience
  4. The Existence of Secondary Qualities
  5. Intentionality
  6. Self-Awareness and Personal Identity through time.
  7. Indexicals. Irreducibility of third-person to first-person.

Functionalism and Computers

Ironically, after half a century of creating devices to mimic and extend human operations and purposes, many now think that it is we who are created in the image of computers, not vice-versa. We are basically organic computers, and because noone thinks computers are one part circuits and one part souls, we likewise are neurons without souls. But, does the operation and analogous functionality of computers suggest that we are like computers? Are any of the above properties exhibited by computers? Might they be?

The computer analogy is basically a modern version of functionalism. In the philosophy of mind, functionalism is the view that the mind should be defined in terms of causal inputs and outputs. Just as a kidney or carburetor is defined in terms of its function, so also the mind should be defined strictly by a certain kind of causal inputs and outputs. Anything that outputs 4 when fed 2+2 is a mind.

The Chinese Room Argument

The most famous objection, by far, to the human/computer analogy is John Searle’s Chinese Room Argument (Scientific American, C2, Searle 1990, 26-27).

Consider a language you don’t understand. In my case, I do not understand Chinese. To me, Chinese writing looks like so many meaningless squiggles. Now suppose I am placed in a room containing baskets full of Chinese symbols. Suppose also that I am given a rule book in English for matching Chinese symbols with other Chinese symbols. The rules identify the symbols entirely by their shapes and do not require that I understand any of them. The rules might say such things as “take a squiggle-squiggle sign from basket number one and put it next to a squoggle-squoggle sign from basket number two.”

Image that people outside the room who understand Chinese hand in small bunches of symbols and that in response I manipulate the symbols according to the rule book and hand back more small bunches of symbols. Now the rule book is the “computer program.” The people who wrote it are the “programmers,” and I am the “computer.” The baskets full of symbols are the “data base,” the small bunches that are handed in to me are “questions” and the bunches I then hand out are “answers.”

Now suppose that the rule book is written in such a way that my “answers” to the “questions” are indistinguishable from those of a native Chinese speaker. For example, the people outside might hand me some symbols that, unknown to me, mean, “What is your favorite color?” and I might after going through the rules give back symbols that, also unknown to me, mean “My favorite color is blue, but I also like green a lot.” I satisfy the Turing test for understanding Chinese. All the same, I am totally ignorant of Chinese. And there is no way I could come to understand Chinese in the system as described, since there is no way that I can learn the meanings of any of the symbols. Like a computer, I manipulate symbols, but I attach no meaning to the symbols.

The point of the thought experiment is this: if I do not understand Chinese solely on the basis of running a computer program for understanding Chinese, then neither does any other digital computer solely on that basis. Digital computers merely manipulate form symbols according to rules in the program.

What goes fro Chinese goes for other forms of cognition as well. Just manipulating symbols is not by itself enough to guarantee cognition, perception, understanding, thinking, and so forth. And since computer, qua computers, are symbol manipulating devices, merely running the computer program is not enough to guarantee cognition.

This simple argument is decisive against the claims of strong AI.

The Implications

In your original response to my article, “The Captain of My Soul”, you said: “I can write a program that will discriminate between conflicting
desires on the basis of reason, desire, and beliefs, and then let it do
so. … The same is true for us. We have an internal deterministic faculty
which discriminates between external desires on the basis of beliefs,
reasons, etc.” I think this is a mistake. Just because we can make a computer take inputs and return outputs in the same way humans do, it does not mean that computers are doing what we do, unless functionalism is true. If we manage to create a perfect Turing machine, it would not mean that that machine would be “thinking” or had “desires” and “beliefs”. There is no reason to think that the flips and switches have any semantic or emotional content. But we know in our own cases that our reasoning and feeling do have such content.

Rush Limbaugh just said: “I know these liberals. I know these cockroaches.” Get the paddle.

In
by

Quantum Physics as Rorschach Test

Go Recently, with reference to the cosmological argument, a friend suggested that quantum physics undercuts the presumption that every event must have a cause, the principle that drives the argument. I cautioned that the significance of the observed phenomena in quantum physics is a matter of such debate that drawing any such implication is tenuous at best, and in any case, quantum indeterminacy doesn't carry beyond the level of elementary particles. This move, he suggested, was typical of Christians and Objectivists, but not of scientists themselves. And ironically, I had just read Christian philosopher J.P. Moreland making this point: "Regarding quantum entities, there are at least eight different empirically equivalent philosophical models of quantuam reality and, at this stage, it is irresponsible to make dogmatic claims about the ontology of the quantum level."1 (20) My sense is that quantum physics, at least on the popular level, operates as a kind of Rorschach Test, amenable to whatever presuppositions one brings to the table. This is why one finds a whole host of viewpoints appropriating "the new physics" to their own ends, from libertarian naturalists to New Age mystics. The quantum level is sometimes described as a wonderland where none of the usual rules apply and anything is impossible. So, what should we infer from quantum physics? And what is its appropriate role in philosophical debate? Relying heavily on those who understand it better than I do, here are a few suggestions.

Common Cause

Go

This comes up again in Craig and Krauss debate.

Luke at Common Sense recently asked Challies about on what atheists and Christians could make common cause.

In
by

Kant’s Godless Morality

Go

It starts off with deontology and ends in radical consequentialism:

  1. The reflective structure of consciousness requires that in order for me to act at all, “I”, the persistent I, must have a set of rules from which to endorse or reject possible courses of action.
  2. Not only am I free to endorse or reject possible courses of action, I am also free to endorse or reject the very set of rules from which I choose to endorse or reject actions.
  3. Such a set of rules will be obligatory for me only because I have chosen them myself, and
  4. The only standard for whether a set of rules will be valid is whether I can reasonably choose them.
  5. I should, therefore, only act on a rule if I can rationally choose it to be the rule I will always behave by.
  6. But since the relevant domain of rules we are evaluating (possible acts) does not distinguish between agents
  7. I should, therefore, only act on a rule if I can rationally choose it to be a universal law for all agents.
  8. Since there is nothing irrational about willing that everyone acting to bring about the best results overall was a universal law, I am permitted to act in that way.
  9. Moreover, since
    (9-1) no other rule than “act to bring about the best results overall” does, in fact, bring about the best results overall, and
    (9-2) I and all agents always want the best results,
  10. The only universal law I can rationally will is that I act to bring about the best results overall. So,
  11. I and all other rational beings are required to promote the best results overall, even if the cost to me is greater than the benefit, as long as the overall benefits are maximized.

Obviously there is much to be said about all of these points, but so far this is the most compelling answer I’ve found to the normative question. Propositions 8-11 are Kagan’s, and I’m much less sure about them, but Kant’s original argument, 1-7 seems only to grow more convincing as I think about them.

What do you think on first look? Although I’m sure I’m doing a bad job representing it, it’s honestly one of the most brilliant and compelling arguments I’ve ever seen.

So as of late I have been obsessing over the apparent attractiveness of Kant’s answer to the normative question, i.e. “Why be moral?” Have you encountered such an approach seriously before? I hadn’t, and it’s blowing my mind. Today I had some time to synthesize my latest understanding, though it’s simply a sketch. It’s taken completely from Shelly Kagan, Christine Korsgaard, who all rely on Kant.

Thoughts

Two ironies immediately come to mind. First, that far from being an analysis that does away with the need for God, Kant saw his own ethic as an argument for God’s existence. Second, as you note, that Kant’s deontological ethics are seen as a rival to consequentialism, not an antecedent to them. So, it’s ironic that Kant’s own thinking led in exactly the opposite direction as your own. What is intriguing then, will be to understand how the categorical imperative fits within the context of his other views and yours. One argument in particular that comes to mind is Kant’s view that categories, like space and time, are features of human consciousness, not of the world in itself.

Kant’s Moral Argument for God

  1. Moral behaviour is rational.
  2. Moral behaviour is only rational if justice will be done.
  3. Justice will only be done if God exists.
  4. Therefore: God exists.

What do you think? Can moral behavior be rational if there is no ultimate justice? If Kant is right, his categorical imperative would be necessary but not sufficient for the rationality of moral action.

In your premise (8), you may be smuggling consequentialism into Kant’s argument where it doesn’t belong.

The theist may step back a level to the Argument from Reason.

A God of Love or of Hate

Go

The handful of Fred Phelps’ family members who comprise Westboro Baptist Church in Topeka, Kansas have garnered national notoriety with a simple message: God hates gays, soldiers, you, me, and basically everyone. Their message is carefully crafted to maximize offense, as are the venues they choose, very often funerals. Their knack for inflammatory rhetoric and self-promotion has earned them almost universal disapprobation. Nevertheless, the Phelps take themselves to be God’s prophets. Their website is replete with biblical references. Their biblical rationale is clearly highlighted. I find myself asking a troubling question. Biblically and theologically, is their gospel of hate defensible? After all, I hear echoes of their theology elsewhere. The Phelps are extreme exemplars of a virulent strain within Calvinistic theology whose mission is the proclamation of what I will call a “gospel of condemnation”. Pickets, placards, and bullhorns are very often their preferred prophetic tools. (Is the medium the message?) God’s imminent judgment in Hell is the predominant theme. Like the Phelps, they are more than eager to play at blblical prooftexting with any and all comers. Indeed, they are especially fond of picketing “Laodicean” Christian events where they can expect to be rifling through scripture with a host of challengers and onlookers. They’ll be chomping at the bit at any mention of John 3:16. And so again, I ask, are they faithfully representing the Bible? Does God hate people? Does God hate wrongdoers? Recently (October 7, 2011), Mark Driscoll of Mars Hill Church sounded similar notes in his thoroughgoing series on the gospel of Luke, stating and restating that “God hates you”, before doubling back confusingly to reassure the listener that “God loves you”. Driscoll is not at all marginal. He is a gifted and highly influential exegete and pastor within Reformed circles. He does his homework and cares about accurately teaching the Bible. Hearing a similar theology of God’s hate from the likes of Driscoll makes it clear that the theology itself cannot be dismissed out of hand. If you had thought, like me, that the Christian gospel was one of God’s boundless, unmerited love for sinners, this theology of God’s hatefulness must be considered on its own terms. So, what does the Bible say?

About Afterall.net

Go

Afterall.net is more or less an online filing cabinet of collected articles and snippets from my quest to find answers to the big questions, especially of faith and reason, plus a fair share of reflections and commentaries from yours truly, Nathan Jacobson. As such, it is my hope that Afterall.net reflects some of my core values: an honest search for the truth of the matter, an appropriate humility regarding our human abilities as truthseekers, and a profound respect for all who presume to address the question, no matter their point of view. For the sake of full disclosure, I come at the question as a Christian, inclined to think (and yes, also hoping) that Christian theism is true. However, my whole adult life my faith has been beset by doubt, and it is this unrelenting uncertainty that compels me to return to the question earnestly, again and again. Doubting Thomas, I guess, is my patron saint. And like Thomas, I really do want to know.

Our Kind of Skepticism

Go

I come lastly to a third type of intellect, in which Twofold Truth presents itself in a moderate and altogether commendable shape; in which the disparity is not so much antagonistic as complementary, and the result of its functions is not disunion and hostility so much as a broad comprehensive solidarity. For our purpose we may call intellects of this class ‘dual-sighted’ or ‘two- eyed.’ … This ‘double-sighted man’ is by no means the synonym of the nickname common in Puritan history, ‘Mr. Facing-both-ways.’ It rather implies the possession of faculties which enable the observer to see every object in the solid, substantial manner, in the full relief, and with the true perspective that pertain essentially to all double vision. It is the instinctive power and tendency to discern a specific object or a given truth not merely as it is in itself or in one of its prima facie aspects, but in its completeness as a whole and relatively to all its surroundings. We see this quality in the artist who simultaneously with the perception of an object also sees all its different phases as well as its relations to surrounding objects; or again in the general who apprehends by a single glance of his mental vision all the characteristics, bad as well as good, of a given position or military movement. So the philosophers I speak of catch every truth or doctrine, not in its simple and uniform, but in its complex biform or multiform aspect. They are men to whom every affirmation suggests, if only as a possibility, a negative; who intuitively meet every dogmatic pronouncement with an objection, just as a painter infers shadow from light. These are the men who in my judgment have rendered the best service to the progress of knowledge by their comprehensive vision, their cautious Skeptical attitude, their fearless criticism. …

Gaps or Chasms

Go

The fourth chapter of The God Delusion is the gravamen of Dawkins’ case that God “almost certainly does not exist”. Here we find Dawkins in his element, tromping through the natural world in awe and wonder, and no one is a better field guide than he, whose descriptions of its beauty and complexity are breathtaking. It’s not surprising that he calls the desire to infer a designer from all this a “temptation”, albeit a temptation that must be resisted. But Dawkins’ evolutionary narrative of what he finds there is as bare as his . So with that in mind, I go where I fear to tread.